Christopher Makler
Stanford University Department of Economics
Econ 50: Lecture 4
๐
๐ฅฅ
Production Possibilities Fronier
Feasible
Labor
Fish
๐
Capital
Coconuts
๐ฅฅ
[GOODS]
โณ
โ
[RESOURCES]
๐
๐ฅฅ
๐
๐
๐
๐ข
๐
How does Chuck rank
all possible combinations
of fish and coconuts?
Goal: find the best combination within his production possibilities set.
Feasible
Part 1: Modeling Preferences with Utility Functions
Part 2: Some "canonical" utility functions
Preferences: Definition and Axioms
Indifference curves
The Marginal Rate of Substitution
Utility Functions
Perfect Substitutes
Perfect Complements
Cobb-Douglas
Quasilinear
Given a choice between option A and option B, an agent might have different preferences:
The agent strictly prefers A to B.
The agent strictly disprefers ย A to B.
The agent weakly prefers ย A to B.
The agent weakly disprefers ย A to B.
The agent is indifferent between A and B.
The agent strictly prefers A to B.
The agent weakly prefers ย A to B.
Complete
Transitive
Any two options can be compared.
If \(A\) is preferred to \(B\), and \(B\) is preferred to \(C\),
then \(A\) is preferred to \(C\).
Together, these assumptions mean that we can rank
all possible choices in a coherent way.
Special case: choosing between bundles
containing different quantities of goods.
Example: โgood 1โ is apples, โgood 2โ is bananas, and โgood 3โ is cantaloupes:
๐๐๐๐
๐๐๐
๐๐๐๐๐๐
๐๐๐
๐๐๐๐๐๐๐๐
๐๐
General framework: choosing between anything
Good 1 \((x_1)\)
Good 2 \((x_2)\)
Completeness axiom:
any two bundles can be compared.
Implication: given any bundle \(A\),
the choice space may be divided
into three regions:
preferred to A
dispreferred to Aย
indifferent to Aย
Indifference curves cannot cross!
๐๐
๐๐
๐๐
๐๐
๐๐
๐๐๐๐
๐๐๐๐
๐๐๐๐
๐๐๐๐
๐๐๐๐
๐๐๐๐
๐๐
๐๐
๐๐
๐๐
๐๐
๐๐
๐๐๐๐
๐๐๐๐
๐๐๐๐
๐๐๐๐
๐๐๐๐
Suppose you were indifferent between the following two bundles:
Starting at bundle X,
you would be willing
to give up 4 bananas
to get 2 apples
Let apples be good 1, and bananas be good 2.
Starting at bundle Y,
you would be willing
to give up 2 apples
to get 4 bananas
Visually: the MRS is the magnitude of the slope
of an indifference curve
How do we model preferences mathematically?
Approach: assume consuming goods "produces" utility
Labor
Fish
๐
Capital
โณ
โ
[RESOURCES]
Utility
๐
[GOODS]
Fish
๐
Coconuts
๐ฅฅ
"A is strictly preferred to B"
Words
Preferences
Utility
"A is weakly preferred to B"
"A is indifferent to B"
"A is weakly dispreferred to B"
"A is strictly dispreferred to B"
Suppose the "utility function"
assigns a real number (in "utils")
to every possible consumption bundle
We get completeness because any two numbers can be compared,
and we get transitivity because that's a property of the operator ">"ย
Given a utility function \(u(x_1,x_2)\),
we can interpret the partial derivativesย
as the "marginal utility" from
another unit of either good:
Along an indifference curve, all bundles will produce the same amount of utility
In other words, each indifference curve
is a level setย of the utility function.
The slope of an indifference curve is the MRS. By the implicit function theorem,
(Note: we'll treat this as a positive number, just like the MRTS and the MRT)
A
B
Do we have to take the
number of "utils" seriously?
Just like the "volume" on an amp, "utils" are an arbitrary scale...saying you're "11" happy from a bundle doesn't mean anything!
Applying a positive monotonic transformationย to a utility function doesn't affect
the way it ranks bundles.
Example: \(\hat u(x_1,x_2) = 2u(x_1,x_2)\)
Applying a positive monotonic transformationย to a utility function doesn't affect
its MRS at any bundle (and therefore generates the same indifference map).
Example: \(\hat u(x_1,x_2) = 2u(x_1,x_2)\)
Applying a positive monotonic transformationย to a utility function doesn't affect
its MRS at any bundle (and therefore generates the same indifference map).
Example: \(\hat u(x_1,x_2) = \ln(u(x_1,x_2))\)
One reason to transform a utility function is to normalizeย it.
This allows us to describe preferences using fewer parameters.
[ multiply by \({1 \over a + b}\) ]
[ let \(\alpha = {a \over a + b}\) ]
We've asserted that all (rational) preferences are completeย and transitive.
There are some additional properties which are true of someย preferences:
Some goods provide positive marginal utility only up to a point, beyond which consuming more of them actually decreasesย your utility.
Strict monotonicity: any increase in any good strictly increases utility (\(MU > 0\) for all goods)
Weak monotonicity: no increase in any good will strictly decrease utility (\(MU \ge 0\) for all goods)
Example: Pfizer's COVID-19 vaccine has a dose of 0.3mL, Moderna's has a dose of 0.5mL
Math background: "Convex combinations"
Take any two bundles, \(A\) and \(B\), between which you are indifferent.
Would you rather have a convex combination of those two bundles,
than have either of those bundles themselves?
If you would always answer yes, your preferences are convex.
Take any two bundles, \(A\) and \(B\), between which you are indifferent.
Would you rather have a convex combination of those two bundles,
than have either of those bundles themselves?
If you would always answer no, your preferences are convex.
1. Convexity does not imply you always want equal numbers of things.
2. It's preferencesย which are convex, not the utility function.
Continuous: utility functions don't have "jumps"
Smooth: marginal utilities don't have "jumps"
Counter-example: vaccine dose example
Counter-example: Leontief/Perfect Complements utility function
If preferences are strictly monotonic, strictly convex, continuous, and smooth, then:
Indifference curves are smooth, downward-sloping, and bowed in toward the origin
The MRS is diminishing as you move down and to the right along an indifference curve
Good 1 \((x_1)\)
Good 2 \((x_2)\)
"Law of Diminishing MRS"
Part I: properties of preferences,
and how preferences can be represented by utility functions.
Part II: see examples of utility functions,
and examine how different functional forms
can be used to model different kinds of preferences.
Take the time to understand this material well.ย
It's foundational for many, many economic models.