Verifiable Characterization of Characteristic subgroups
https://slides.com/jameswilson-3/what-is-difference/
James B. Wilson, Colorado State University
1. Show which graphs are the same.
-4 Need to show how to build an isomorphism between these
2. Show which graphs are the same.
Great, maybe add labels to the different edges in the same color.
1. Show \(D_8\) is not the same as \(Q_8\).
-4 need to identify different structure,
e.g count the number of elements of order 2
1. Show which graphs are the same.
Great.
Auckland
Galway
Bucknell
Monash
Things are different when they have different "structure", i.e. logical operations separate them.
Need isomorphisms, i.e. a category
It is often said:
"The character table is an invariant of finite groups."
What is "the" character table? This is non unique.
Reality
Definiton. In a category \(C\) an invariant is a functor \(I:C\to P\) into a partial order \(P=\langle P,\leq \rangle\)
Claim: Isomorphism invariant
\[X\cong Y \Rightarrow I(X)=I(Y)\]
is alway implied.
Theorem (B-M-O'B-W)
Theorem (B-M-O'B-W)
Every* isomorphism invariant \(I:\overset{\leftrightarrow}{C}\to P\) is into a poset.
*Univalence/ Cantor-Schroder-Bernstein
Corollary. Isomorphism invariants define a distance function (pseudo-matric):
\(u\cong v\Rightarrow d(u,v)=0\)
Distance induced by chromatic number of graph
Definition. An invariant \(I:C\to P\) is characteristic if for every automorphism \(\varphi\) of \(P\),
\[\varphi(I(X)) = X\]
A characteristic invariant is the only family of invariant that is solely about C (no parameters) and isn't replacing isomorphism.
Theorem (B-M-O'B-W) There are categories with
Toy Example: category of 4 vertex graphs <3 edges under inclusion
Easy invariants:
Perhaps "structure" comes from outside.
Break symmetry of invariants by extending context
Characteristic: \(H\leq G\) for every automorphism \(\varphi:G\to G\), \[\varphi(H)=H\]
Looks structural.
Rottlaender Type Groups:
\[\left\{\begin{bmatrix} \alpha & & u \\ & \alpha^u & v \\ & & 1 \end{bmatrix}\right\}\]
Has characteristic subgroups \[\left\{\begin{bmatrix} 1 & & u\\ & 1 & 0 \\ & & 1\end{bmatrix}\right\},\left\{\begin{bmatrix}1& & 0 \\ & 1 & v\\ & & 1 \end{bmatrix}\right\}\] but which is which? This is non-structural!
Characteristic: \(H\leq G\) for every automorphism \(\varphi:G\to G\), \[\varphi(H)=H\]
Looks structural.
Good Characteristic, e.g. commutator, come from external structure.
Characteristic Subgroups as Category Theory
\[\{\iota:H\hookrightarrow G \mid \iota(H)\text{ char. } G\}=\left\{\iota_G \mid \iota \in \text{Counital}\left(\overset{\longleftrightarrow}{Grp},Grp\right) \right\}\]
Furthermore, every counital is induced by a counit (e.g. all adjoints).
Category \(E\) with subcategory \(A\), \(I:A\hookrightarrow E\)
\[\text{Counital}\left(A,B\right)=\left\{\iota:C\Rightarrow I\right\}\]
Counit = counital with \(A=E, I=id_E\)
Corollary. All characteristic structure is external.
I.e. why a group \(G\) fixes a subgroup is the influence of some category.
Most of categories today is written by topology and geometry.
We think algebra offers something different, and so did Freyd, Scedrov, and few others.
bases Objects \(ob(C)\) a type of data
Morphisms: disjoint sets \(\hom_C(X,Y)\) for objects \((X,Y)\)
operators \(\circ:\hom_C(X,Y)\times \hom_C(Y,Z)\to \hom_C(X,Z)\)
\(1_X\in\hom_C(X,X)\)
rewriting for \(f:\hom_(X,Y), g\in \hom_C(Y,Z), h\in \hom_C(Z,W)\)
\[\begin{aligned} f1_X & = X \\ 1_Y f & = f\\ f(gh) & = (fg)h \end{aligned}\]
2 sorted second order theory
Objects have no axioms in category theory,
they are aren't needed.
base \(A\) a type of data
operators \([\ldots]:A^n\to A^?\) read as "maybe \(A\)"
guard rails polynomial formulas \(\Phi,\Upsilon\) in the operators where
\(\Phi(a_1,\ldots,a_n)=\Upsilon(a_1,\ldots,a_n)\;\Longrightarrow\;[a_1,\ldots,a_n]\text{ defined.}\)
rewriting e.g.\ associative when defined, identity when defined.
base \(A\) a type of data
operators \(\circ:A\times A\to A^?\) a partial product (\(A^?\) reads "maybe A")
\(\lhd(-):A\to A\) and \((-)\lhd:A\to A\)
guard rails \(a\lhd=\lhd\acute{a}\;\Longrightarrow\;a\dot{a}\text{ defined.}\)
rewriting
Summary: Set \(\mathbf{1}_{A}=\{a\lhd \mid a:A\}=\{\lhd a\mid a:A\}\) then
\[\begin{aligned} a(\dot a\ddot a) & = (a\dot a)\ddot a & \mathbf{1}_Aa & = \{a\}=a\mathbf{1}_A\end{aligned}\]
Categories = Monoids with some undefined products
\[\begin{aligned}\lhd(a\lhd) &=a\lhd & (\lhd a)\lhd & = \lhd a\\ \lhd(a\dot a) & =\lhd a & (a \dot a)\lhd & = \dot a\lhd\\ a(a\lhd) & = a & (\lhd a)a & = a \\ a(\dot a\ddot a)& =(a \dot a)\ddot a \end{aligned}\]
Given \(f\in\hom_C(X,Y)\) and \(g\in hom_C(X',Y')\) define
\[f\sqcup g:=\{f,g\}\subset \hom_C(X,Y)\cup \hom_C(X',Y')\]
Facts: Set \[A=\bigsqcup_{X,Y}\hom_C(X,Y)\] and identify \(f=\{f\}\)
*In a hierarchy of sets or types.
Facts: Set \(A=\bigsqcup_{X,Y}\hom_C(X,Y)\) and identify \(f=\{f\}\)
\(A\) is a partial associative unital distributive algebra (lacks negatives).
Consequences. Categories \(A\) are much like rings.
\[\mathbf{1}_A = \bigsqcup_{X:ob(C)} 1_X = \begin{bmatrix} 1 & & & \\ & 1 & & \\ & & \ddots & \\ & & & 1 \end{bmatrix}\]
Slice category
Coslice category
Hom-set
As rings have modules,
categories \(A\) have "capsules" \(X\)
\[\cdot:A\times X\to X^?\]
An \(A\)-morphism \[M:X\to Y^?\] where when the left-hand side is defined then \[M(ax)=aM(x)\]
In Peirce decomposition terms
\[\begin{bmatrix} & \vdots & \\ \cdots & A_{ij} & \cdots \\ & \vdots & \end{bmatrix} \begin{bmatrix} \vdots \\ x_j \\ \vdots\end{bmatrix}\]
Facts.
Extension Theorem in Category Theory Language.
In a category \(E\) of eastern algebras, given a counital \(\rho:C\Rightarrow I\) on a subcategory \(A\leq E\). If \(A\leq C\leq E\) and \(A\) is full in \(C\), then there exists a counital \(\sigma:D\Rightarrow J\) on \(C\).
Extension Theorem in Algebra Terms.
Set \(\Delta=A\rho A\). Then there is capsule \(\Upsilon\) where
\[\Delta\cong \text{Res}_A^C(\text{Ind}_A^C(\Delta))\otimes_A \Upsilon\]
Corollary. All characteristic subgroups come from externalities.
Theorem.
Commutator subgroup is the kernel of abelian adjunction (external)
Maringal subgroups externalized by Varieties
All our theorems have been done with minimal logic (Intuitionistic Martin-Lof). Consequence?