pollev.com/chrismakler
How secure are you feeling about the material from Wednesday?
Characteristics of Utility Functions
Christopher Makler
Stanford University Department of Economics
Econ 50: Lecture 6
Today's Agenda
- Review some ways to draw indifference curves
- Analyze properties of preferences and utility
- Look at some specific utility functions and the preferences they represent
Example: draw the indifference curve for u(x1,x2)=21x1x22 passing through (4,6).
Step 1: Evaluate u(x1,x2) at the point
Step 2: Set u(x1,x2) equal to that value.
Step 4: Plug in various values of x1 and plot!
u(4,6)=21×4×62=72
21x1x22=72
x22=x144
x2=x112
How to Draw an Indifference Curve through a Point: Method I
Step 3: Solve for x2.
How would this have been different if the utility function were u(x1,x2)=x1×x2?
u(4,6)=4×6=12
x1×x2=12
x2=x112
Example: draw the indifference curve for u(x1,x2)=21x1x22 passing through (4,6).
Step 1: Derive MRS(x1,x2). Determine its characteristics: is it smoothly decreasing? Constant?
Step 2: Evaluate MRS(x1,x2) at the point.
Step 4: Sketch the right shape of the curve, so that it's tangent to the line at the point.
How to Draw an Indifference Curve through a Point: Method II
Step 3: Draw a line passing through the point with slope −MRS(x1,x2)
How would this have been different if the utility function were u(x1,x2)=x1×x2?
This is continuously strictly decreasing in x1 and continuously strictly increasing in x2,
so the function is smooth and strictly convex and has the "normal" shape.
Desirable Properties of Preferences
We've asserted that all (rational) preferences are complete and transitive.
There are some additional properties which are true of some preferences:
- Monotonicity
- Convexity
- Continuity
- Smoothness
Monotonic Preferences: “More is Better"
Strict vs. Weak Monotonicity
Strict monotonicity: any increase in any good strictly increases utility (MU>0 for all goods)
Weak monotonicity: no increase in any good will strictly decrease utility (MU≥0 for all goods)
Example: Pfizer's COVID-19 vaccine has a dose of 0.3mL, Moderna's has a dose of 0.5mL
Convex Preferences: “Variety is Better"
Take any two bundles, A and B, between which you are indifferent.
Would you rather have a convex combination of those two bundles,
than have either of those bundles themselves?
If you would always answer yes, your preferences are convex.
Common Mistakes about Convexity
1. Convexity does not imply you always want equal numbers of things.
2. It's preferences which are convex, not the utility function.
Other Desirable Properties
Continuous: utility functions don't have "jumps"
Smooth: marginal utilities don't have "jumps"
Counter-example: vaccine dose example
Counter-example: Leontief/Perfect Complements utility function
Well-Behaved Preferences
If preferences are strictly monotonic, strictly convex, continuous, and smooth, then:
Indifference curves are smooth, downward-sloping, and bowed in toward the origin
The MRS is diminishing as you move down and to the right along an indifference curve
Good 1 (x1)
Good 2 (x2)
"Law of Diminishing MRS"
Preferences over Soda
Suppose one liter of soda gives you 20 "utils" of utility; so each one-liter bottle (good 1) gives you 20 utils,
and each two-liter bottle (good 2) gives you 40 utils.
Which other bundles give you the same utility as
12 one-liter bottles and 6 two-liter bottles (A)?
Which other bundles give you the same utility as
12 one-liter bottles and 2 two-liter bottle (B)?
12
24
Any combination that has 24 total liters
Any combination that has 16 total liters
16
20
4
8
12
24
16
20
4
8
A
B
pollev.com/chrismakler
Preferences over Soda
Suppose one liter of soda gives you 20 "utils" of utility; so each one-liter bottle (good 1) gives you 20 utils,
and each two-liter bottle (good 2) gives you 40 utils.
Which other bundles give you the same utility as
12 one-liter bottles and 6 two-liter bottles (A)?
Which other bundles give you the same utility as
12 one-liter bottles and 2 two-liter bottle (B)?
Any combination that has 24 total liters
Any combination that has 16 total liters
What utility function represents these preferences?
Perfect Substitutes
Goods that can always be exchanged at a constant rate.
-
Red pencils and blue pencils, if you con't care about color
-
One-dollar bills and five-dollar bills
-
One-liter bottles of soda and two-liter bottles of soda
Preferences over Tea and Biscuits
Charlotte always has 2 biscuits with every cup of tea;
if she has a plate of biscuits and one cup of tea, she'll only eat two. (And if she has a whole pot of tea and 6 biscuits, she'll stop pouring after 3 cups of tea.)
Each (cup + 2 biscuits) gives her 10 utils of joy.
Which other bundles give her the same utility as
3 cups of tea and 4 biscuits (A)?
Which other bundles give her the same utility as
1 cup of tea and 4 biscuits (B)?
3
6
Any combination that has 4 biscuits
and 2 or more cups of tea
Any combination that has 1 cup of tea and
at 2 or more biscuits
4
5
1
2
3
6
4
5
1
2
A
B
Normalizing Utility Functions
One reason to transform a utility function is to normalize it.
This allows us to describe preferences using fewer parameters.
[ multiply by a+b1 ]
[ let α=a+ba ]
pollev.com/chrismakler
What utility function represents these preferences?
Preferences over Tea and Biscuits
Charlotte always has 2 biscuits with every cup of tea;
if she has a plate of biscuits and one cup of tea, she'll only eat two. (And if she has a whole pot of tea and 6 biscuits, she'll stop pouring after 3 cups of tea.)
Each (cup + 2 biscuits) gives her 10 utils of joy.
Which other bundles give her the same utility as
3 cups of tea and 4 biscuits (A)?
Which other bundles give her the same utility as
1 cup of tea and 4 biscuits (B)?
Any combination that has 4 biscuits
and 2 or more cups of tea
Any combination that has 1 cup of tea and
at 2 or more biscuits
Perfect Complements
Goods that you like to consume
in a constant ratio.
Left shoes and right shoes
Sugar and tea
Cobb-Douglas
An easy mathematical form with interesting properties.
-
Used for two independent goods (neither complements nor substitutes) -- e.g., t-shirts vs hamburgers
-
Also called "constant shares" for reasons we'll see later.
Normalizing Cobb-Douglas Functions
One reason to transform a utility function is to normalize it.
This allows us to describe preferences using fewer parameters.
[ multiply by a+b1 ]
[ let α=a+ba ]
Normalizing Cobb-Douglas Functions
One reason to transform a utility function is to normalize it.
This allows us to describe preferences using fewer parameters.
[ raise to the power of a+b1 ]
[ let α=a+ba ]
Quasilinear
Generally used when Good 2 is
"dollars spent on other things."
-
Marginal utility of good 2 is constant
-
If good 2 is "dollars spent on other things," utility from good 1 is often given as if it were in dollars.
Concave
The opposite of convex: as you consume more of a good, you become more willing to give up others
-
MRS is increasing in x1 and/or decreasing in x2
-
Indifference curves are bowed away from the origin.
Satiation Point
There is some ideal bundle; utility falls off as you move away from that bundle
-
Not monotonic
-
Realistic, but often the satiation point is far out of reach.
“Semi-Satiated"
One good has an ideal quantity; the other doesn't
-
Can be a combination of quasilinear and satiation point
-
Can generate the familiar linear demand curve
Curve Balls
Good 1: chocolate chip cookies
Good 2: snickerdoodle cookies
Good 3: vanilla ice cream
Good 4: strawberry ice cream
Curve Balls
Good 1: burritos
Good 2: burgers
Good 3: fries
Curve Balls
Good 1: fries
Good 2: onion rings
Good 3: burgers
Summary
When considering two goods, there are lots of ways you might feel about them — especially how substitutable the goods are for one another, which is captured by the MRS.
Different functional forms have different MRS's; so they're good for modeling different kinds of preferences.
Take the time to understand this material well.
It's foundational for many, many economic models.
Econ 50 | Lecture 06
By Chris Makler
Econ 50 | Lecture 06
Characteristics of Utility Functions
- 581