20 Years of Tameness
Monica VanDieren
November 17, 2021
Tameness
Limit Models
First Order Theories
1
First Order Theories
\(L_{\omega_1,\omega}\) Theories
Incomplete Map of Non-elementary Classes
1
First Order Theories
\(L_{\omega_1,\omega}\) Theories
Incomplete Map of Non-elementary Classes
1
First Order Theories
\(L_{\omega_1,\omega}\) Theories
\(L_{\kappa^+,\omega}\) Theories
Incomplete Map of Non-elementary Classes
1
First Order Theories
\(L_{\omega_1,\omega}\) Theories
\(L_{\kappa^+,\omega}\) Theories
Abstract Elementary Classes
Incomplete Map of Non-elementary Classes
1
First Order Theories
\(L_{\omega_1,\omega}\) Theories
\(L_{\kappa^+,\omega}\) Theories
Abstract Elementary Classes
Tame
Incomplete Map of Non-elementary Classes
2
First Order Theories
\(L_{\omega_1,\omega}\) Theories
\(L_{\kappa^+,\omega}\) Theories
Abstract Elementary Classes
Universal, Homogeneous, Finitary
Non-elementary Classes
Tame
2
Abstract Elementary Classes
Classification Theory for
Tame
3
Abstract Elementary Classes
Classification Theory for
Tame
Categorical in high enough cardinality
3
Abstract Elementary Classes
Classification Theory for
Tame
Categorical in high enough cardinality
Stable
3
Abstract Elementary Classes
Classification Theory for
Tame
Categorical in high enough cardinality
Stable
Superstable
3
Test Question for
Classification Theory of AECs
First Order Morley's Theorem: Suppose \(T\) is a countable complete first order theory. If there exists an uncountable \(\lambda\) such that \(T\) is \(\lambda\) categorical, then \(T\) is \(\mu\)-categorical in all uncountable \(\mu\).
4
Test Question for
Classification Theory of AECs
Infinitary Logic Conjecture (Shelah, 1976): Suppose \(\psi\in L_{\omega_1,\omega}\) in a countable language. If there exists a \(\lambda\geq\beth_{\omega_1}\) such that \(\psi\) is \(\lambda\) categorical, then \(\psi\) is \(\mu\)-categorical in all \(\mu\geq \beth_{\omega_1}\).
First Order Morley's Theorem: Suppose \(T\) is a countable complete first order theory. If there exists an uncountable \(\lambda\) such that \(T\) is \(\lambda\) categorical, then \(T\) is \(\mu\)-categorical in all uncountbale \(\mu\).
4
Test Question for
Classification Theory of AECs
Infinitary Logic Conjecture (Shelah, 1976): Suppose \(\psi\in L_{\omega_1,\omega}\) in a countable language. If there exists a \(\lambda\geq\beth_{\omega_1}\) such that \(\psi\) is \(\lambda\) categorical, then \(\psi\) is \(\mu\)-categorical in all \(\mu\geq \beth_{\omega_1}\).
AEC Conjecture: Suppose \(\mathcal{K}\) is an AEC in a language of cardinality \(LS(\mathcal{K})\). If there exists a \(\lambda \geq \beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)\(^*\) such that \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\lambda\)-categorical, then \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\mu\)-categorical in all \(\mu\geq \beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\).
First Order Morley's Theorem: Suppose \(T\) is a countable complete first order theory. If there exists an uncountable \(\lambda\) such that \(T\) is \(\lambda\) categorical, then \(T\) is \(\mu\)-categorical in all uncountbale \(\mu\).
\(^*\) This bound is smaller when \(LS(\mathcal{K})=\aleph_0\).
4
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
5
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
If \(M\in\mathcal{K}\) and \(M\cong N\), then \(N\in\mathcal{K}\).
5
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
6
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
If \(M,N\in\mathcal{K}\) and \(M\prec N\),
then \(M\) is a submodel of \(N\).
6
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
If \(M\prec M^*\), \(N\prec M^*\), and \(M\subseteq N\),
then \(M\prec N\)
7
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
If \(M\prec M^*\), \(N\prec M^*\), and \(M\subseteq N\),
then \(M\prec N\)
\(M\)
\(M^*\)
7
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
If \(M\prec M^*\), \(N\prec M^*\), and \(M\subseteq N\),
then \(M\prec N\)
\(N\)
\(M^*\)
7
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
If \(M\prec M^*\), \(N\prec M^*\), and \(M\subseteq N\),
then \(M\prec N\)
\(M\)
\(N\)
\(M^*\)
7
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
If \(M\prec M^*\), \(N\prec M^*\), and \(M\subseteq N\),
then \(M\preceq N\).
\(M\)
\(N\)
\(M^*\)
7
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
8
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
\(A\)
\(M\)
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
There exists \(\lambda = LS(\mathcal{K})\) such that for every \(M\in\mathcal{K}\) and for every \(A\subseteq M\), there exists \(N\in\mathcal{K}\) so that \(N\prec M\) and \(\|N\|\leq |A|+\lambda\).
8
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
\(A\)
\(N\)
\(M\)
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
There exists \(\lambda=LS(\mathcal{K})\) such that for every \(M\in\mathcal{K}\) and for every \(A\subseteq M\), there exists \(N\in\mathcal{K}\) so that \(N\preceq M\) and \(\|N\|\leq |A|+\lambda\).
8
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
A5a. Union Conditions
9
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
\(M_0\)
\(M_i\)
\(M_{i+1}\)
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
If \(\langle M_i\in\mathcal{K}\mid i<\alpha\rangle\) is an \(\prec\)-increasing sequence, then \(\bigcup_{i<\alpha}M_i\in\mathcal{K}\) and for each \(i<\alpha\), \(M_i\prec \bigcup_{i<\alpha}M_i\).
A5a. Union Conditions
. . .
. . .
9
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
\(M_0\)
\(M_i\)
\(M_{i+1}\)
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
If \(\langle M_i\in\mathcal{K}\mid i<\alpha\rangle\) is an \(\prec\)-increasing sequence, then \(\bigcup_{i<\alpha}M_i\in\mathcal{K}\) and for each \(i<\alpha\), \(M_i\prec \bigcup_{i<\alpha}M_i\).
A5a. Union Conditions
. . .
. . .
\(\bigcup_{i<\alpha}M_{i}\)
9
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
\(M_i\)
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
If \(\langle M_i\in\mathcal{K}\mid i<\alpha\rangle\) is an \(\prec\)-increasing sequence, then \(\bigcup_{i<\alpha}M_i\in\mathcal{K}\) and for each \(i<\alpha\), \(M_i\prec \bigcup_{i<\alpha}M_i\).
A5a. Union Conditions
\(\bigcup_{i<\alpha}M_{i}\)
\(M_0\)
\(M_{i+1}\)
. . .
. . .
9
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
A5a.
A5b. Union Conditions
10
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
\(M_0\)
\(M_i\)
\(M_{i+1}\)
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
If \(\langle M_i\in\mathcal{K}\mid i<\alpha\rangle\) is an \(\prec\)-increasing sequence and \(N\) is such that for each \(i<\alpha\), \(M_i\prec N\), then \(\bigcup_{i<\alpha}M_i\prec N\).
. . .
. . .
A5a.
A5b. Union Conditions
10
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
\(M_0\)
\(M_i\)
\(M_{i+1}\)
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
If \(\langle M_i\in\mathcal{K}\mid i<\alpha\rangle\) is an \(\prec\)-increasing sequence and \(N\) is such that for each \(i<\alpha\), \(M_i\prec N\), then \(\bigcup_{i<\alpha}M_i\prec N\).
A5b. Union Conditions
. . .
. . .
\(N\)
A5a.
10
AEC Definition
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
\(M_0\)
\(M_i\)
\(M_{i+1}\)
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
If \(\langle M_i\in\mathcal{K}\mid i<\alpha\rangle\) is an \(\prec\)-increasing sequence and \(N\) is such that for each \(i<\alpha\), \(M_i\prec N\), then \(\bigcup_{i<\alpha}M_i\preceq N\).
A5b. Union Conditions
. . .
. . .
\(\bigcup_{i<\alpha}M_{i}\)
\(N\)
A5a.
10
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
Amalgamation Property
A5. Union Conditions
\(N\)
\(M_2\)
\(M_1\)
11
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
Amalgamation Property
A5. Union Conditions
\(N\)
\(M_2\)
\(M'\)
\(M_1\)
11
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
Amalgamation Property
A5. Union Conditions
\(N\)
\(M_2\)
\(M'\)
\(f\)
\(M_1\)
11
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
Amalgamation Property
A5. Union Conditions
\(N\)
\(M_2\)
\(M'\)
\(f\)
\(f(M_1)\)
\(M_1\)
11
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
Amalgamation Property
A5. Union Conditions
\(N\)
\(M_2\)
\(M'\)
\(f\)
\(f(M_1)\)
\(M_1\)
\(f\restriction N=id_N\)
11
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
AP
A5. Union Conditions
Joint Embedding Property
\(M_1\)
\(M_2\)
12
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
AP
A5. Union Conditions
Joint Embedding Property
\(M_1\)
\(M_2\)
\(M'\)
12
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
A5. Union Conditions
Joint Embedding Property
\(f_1(M_1)\)
\(f_2(M_2)\)
\(M'\)
\(f_1\)
\(f_2\)
\(M_1\)
\(M_2\)
AP
12
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
A5. Union Conditions
\(M\)
No Maximal Models
AP
JEP
13
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
A5. Union Conditions
\(M\)
No Maximal Models
\(M'\)
AP
JEP
13
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
AP
A5. Union Conditions
JEP
No Maximal Models
This implies the existence of a monster model.
\(M\)
14
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
AP
A5. Union Conditions
JEP
No Maximal Models
This implies the existence of a monster model, \(\frak{C}\).
\(\frak{C}\)
\(M\)
14
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
AP
A5. Union Conditions
JEP
No Maximal Models
\(M'\)
This implies the existence of a monster model, \(\frak{C}\).
\(\frak{C}\)
\(f\)
\(M\)
14
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
AP
A5. Union Conditions
JEP
\(M\)
No Maximal Models
\(M'\)
This implies the existence of a monster model, \(\frak{C}\).
\(\frak{C}\)
\(f\)
\(f(M')\)
\(f\restriction M=id_M\)
14
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
AP
A5. Union Conditions
JEP
\(A\)
No Maximal Models
This implies the existence of a monster model, \(\frak{C}\).
\(\frak{C}\)
Allowing us to define (Galois) types over models.
15
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
AP
A5. Union Conditions
JEP
\(A\)
No Maximal Models
This implies the existence of a monster model, \(\frak{C}\).
\(\frak{C}\)
Allowing us to define (Galois) types.
\(tp(a/A)=tp(b/A)\)
\(a\)
\(b\)
15
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
AP
A5. Union Conditions
JEP
\(A\)
No Maximal Models
This implies the existence of a monster model, \(\frak{C}\).
\(\frak{C}\)
Allowing us to define (Galois) types.
\(tp(a/A)=tp(b/A)\)
\(a\)
\(M_a\)
\(M_b\)
\(b\)
15
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
AP
A5. Union Conditions
JEP
\(A\)
No Maximal Models
This implies the existence of a monster model, \(\frak{C}\).
\(\frak{C}\)
Allowing us to define (Galois) types.
\(tp(a/A)=tp(b/A)\) iff there exists \(f\) an automophism of \(\frak{C}\)
\(a\)
\(M_a\)
\(M_b\)
\(f\)
\(b\)
15
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
AP
A5. Union Conditions
JEP
\(A\)
No Maximal Models
This implies the existence of a monster model, \(\frak{C}\).
\(\frak{C}\)
Allowing us to define (Galois) types.
\(tp(a/A)=tp(b/A)\) iff there exists \(f\) an automophism of \(\frak{C}\)
so that \(f\restriction A=id_A\) and
\(a\)
\(b\)
\(M_a\)
\(M_b\)
\(f\)
\(f\restriction A=id_A\)
15
Our Setting
\(\mathcal{K}\) is a class of models in a fixed language \(L(\mathcal{K})\) with a partial ordering, \(\prec\), satisfying:
A1. Closure under isomorphisms
A2. Extends submodel relation
A3. Coherence
A4. Löwenheim Skolem
AP
A5. Union Conditions
JEP
\(A\)
No Maximal Models
This implies the existence of a monster model, \(\frak{C}\).
\(\frak{C}\)
Allowing us to define (Galois) types.
\(tp(a/A)=tp(b/A)\) iff there exists \(f\) an automophism of \(\frak{C}\)
so that \(f\restriction A=id_A\) and \(f(a)=b\).
\(a\)
\(b=f(a)\)
\(M_a\)
\(M_b\)
\(f\)
\(f(M_a)\)
\(f\restriction A=id_A\)
15
Our Setting - Tame AECs
\(\mathcal{K}\) is an Abstract Elementary Class satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
A class is \(\chi\)-tame if for every \(N\in\mathcal{K}\) of cardinality \(\geq\chi\), and for every pair of types over \(N\), if \(q_a=tp(a/N)\neq tp(b/N)=q_b\) there exists \(A\subseteq N\) of cardinality \(<\chi\), so that \(q_a\restriction A\neq q_b\restriction A\).
\(\frak{C}\)
\(a\)
\(b\)
\(N\)
16
Our Setting - Tame AECs
\(\mathcal{K}\) is an Abstract Elementary Class satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
A class is \(\chi\)-tame if for every \(N\in\mathcal{K}\) of cardinality \(\geq\chi\), and for every pair of types over \(N\), if \(q_a=tp(a/N)\neq tp(b/N)=q_b\) there exists \(M\prec N\) of cardinality \(<\chi\), so that \(q_a\restriction M\neq q_b\restriction M\).
\(\frak{C}\)
\(a\)
\(N\)
In other words, if \(tp(a/M)=tp(b/M)\) for every \(M\subseteq N\) of cardinality \(<\chi\), then \(tp (a/N)=tp(b/N)\).
\(M\)
\(b\)
16
Our Setting - Tame AECs
\(\mathcal{K}\) is an Abstract Elementary Class satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
A class is \(\chi\)-tame if for every \(N\in\mathcal{K}\) of cardinality \(\geq\chi\), and for every pair of types over \(N\), if \(q_a=tp(a/N)\neq tp(b/N)=q_b\) there exists \(M\prec N\) of cardinality \(<\chi\), so that \(q_a\restriction M\neq q_b\restriction M\).
\(\frak{C}\)
\(a\)
\(b=f_M(a)\)
\(f_M(N)\)
In other words, if \(tp(a/M)=tp(b/M)\) for every \(M\prec N\) of cardinality \(<\chi\), then \(tp (a/N)=tp(b/N)\).
\(M\)
\(f_M\)
\(f_M\restriction M=id_M\)
\(N\)
16
Our Setting - Tame AECs
\(\mathcal{K}\) is an Abstract Elementary Class satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
A class is \(\chi\)-tame if for every \(N\in\mathcal{K}\) of cardinality \(\geq\chi\), and for every pair of types over \(N\), if \(q_a=tp(a/N)\neq tp(b/N)=q_b\) there exists \(M\prec N\) of cardinality \(<\chi\), so that \(q_a\restriction M\neq q_b\restriction M\).
\(\frak{C}\)
\(a\)
\(N\)
In other words, if \(tp(a/M)=tp(b/M)\) for every \(M\prec N\) of cardinality \(<\chi\), then \(tp (a/N)=tp(b/N)\).
\(M'\)
\(b\)
\(N\)
16
Our Setting - Tame AECs
\(\mathcal{K}\) is an Abstract Elementary Class satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
A class is \(\chi\)-tame if for every \(N\in\mathcal{K}\) of cardinality \(\geq\chi\), and for every pair of types over \(N\), if \(q_a=tp(a/N)\neq tp(b/N)=q_b\) there exists \(M\prec N\) of cardinality \(<\chi\), so that \(q_a\restriction M\neq q_b\restriction M\).
\(\frak{C}\)
\(a\)
\(b=f_{M'}(a)\)
\(f_{M'}(N)\)
In other words, if \(tp(a/M)=tp(b/M)\) for every \(M\prec N\) of cardinality \(<\chi\), then \(tp (a/N)=tp(b/N)\).
\(M'\)
\(f_{M'}\)
\(f_{M'}\restriction M'=id_{M'}\)
\(N\)
16
Our Setting - Tame AECs
\(\mathcal{K}\) is an Abstract Elementary Class satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
A class is \(\chi\)-tame if for every \(N\in\mathcal{K}\) of cardinality \(\geq\chi\), and for every pair of types over \(N\), if \(q_a=tp(a/N)\neq tp(b/N)=q_b\) there exists \(M\prec N\) of cardinality \(<\chi\), so that \(q_a\restriction M\neq q_b\restriction M\).
\(\frak{C}\)
\(a\)
\(N\)
In other words, if \(tp(a/M)=tp(b/M)\) for every \(M\prec N\) of cardinality \(<\chi\), then \(tp (a/N)=tp(b/N)\).
\(M''\)
\(b\)
\(N\)
16
Our Setting - Tame AECs
\(\mathcal{K}\) is an Abstract Elementary Class satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
A class is \(\chi\)-tame if for every \(N\in\mathcal{K}\) of cardinality \(\geq\chi\), and for every pair of types over \(N\), if \(q_a=tp(a/N)\neq tp(b/N)=q_b\) there exists \(M\prec N\) of cardinality \(<\chi\), so that \(q_a\restriction M\neq q_b\restriction M\).
\(\frak{C}\)
\(a\)
\(f_{M''}(N)\)
In other words, if \(tp(a/M)=tp(b/M)\) for every \(M\prec N\) of cardinality \(<\chi\), then \(tp (a/N)=tp(b/N)\).
\(M''\)
\(f_{M''}\)
\(b=f_{M''}(a)\)
\(f_{M''}\restriction M''=id_{M''}\)
\(N\)
16
Our Setting - Tame AECs
\(\mathcal{K}\) is an Abstract Elementary Class satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
A class is \(\chi\)-tame if for every \(N\in\mathcal{K}\) of cardinality \(\geq\chi\), and for every pair of types over \(N\), if \(q_a=tp(a/N)\neq tp(b/N)=q_b\) there exists \(M\prec N\) of cardinality \(<\chi\), so that \(q_a\restriction M\neq q_b\restriction M\).
\(\frak{C}\)
\(a\)
\(N\)
In other words, if \(tp(a/M)=tp(b/M)\) for every \(M\prec N\) of cardinality \(<\chi\), then \(tp (a/N)=tp(b/N)\).
\(b\)
16
Our Setting - Tame AECs
\(\mathcal{K}\) is an Abstract Elementary Class satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
Definition (Grossberg-V) A class is \(\chi\)-tame if for every \(N\in\mathcal{K}\) of cardinality \(\geq\chi\), and for every pair of types over \(N\), if \(q_a=tp(a/N)\neq tp(b/N)=q_b\) there exists \(M\prec N\) of cardinality \(<\chi\), so that \(q_a\restriction M\neq q_b\restriction M\).
\(\frak{C}\)
\(a\)
\(N\)
In other words, if \(tp(a/M)=tp(b/M)\) for every \(M\prec N\) of cardinality \(<\chi\), then \(tp (a/N)=tp(b/N)\).
\(b=f_N(a)\)
\(f_N\)
\(f_N\restriction N=id_N\)
16
Why study tameness?
17
Tame AECs are "Everywhere"
-
\(Mod(\psi)\) where \(\psi\in L_{\kappa,\omega}\) with \(\kappa\) strongly compact (Makkai-Shelah)
-
Homogeneous Classes
- Finitary Classes
- Quasi-minimal class axiomatizing Schanuel's Conjecture (Zilber)
- Excellent classes (Kolesnikov-Grossberg)
- Universal classes (Boney)
- All AECs are tame iff there is class many almost strongly compact cardinals (Boney, Boney-Unger)
17
Tameness Informs Work on Shelah's Categoricity Conj.
\(^*\) This bound is smaller when \(LS(\mathcal{K})=\aleph_0\).
Until 2006 most related results
involved set theoretic assumptions.
Shelah's Categoricity Conjecture (1970s): Suppose \(\mathcal{K}\) is an AEC in a language of cardinality \(LS(\mathcal{K})\). If there exists a \(\lambda \geq \beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)\(^*\) such that \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\lambda\)-categorical, then \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\mu\)-categorical in all \(\mu\geq \beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\).
18
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\beth_{\omega_1}<\mu<\lambda^+\).
Downward Categoricity Transfer (Shelah, 1999)
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be an AEC satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
\(\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\)
\(\beth_{\omega_1}\)
categoricity in \(\lambda^+\)
categoricity in \(\lambda^+\)
\(\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)
19
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\beth_{\omega_1}<\mu<\lambda^+\).
Downward Categoricity Transfer (Shelah, 1999)
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be an AEC satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
\(\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\)
\(\beth_{\omega_1}\)
categoricity in \(\mu\)
categoricity in \(\lambda^+\)
\(\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)
19
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\beth_{\omega_1}<\mu<\lambda^+\).
Downward Categoricity Transfer (Shelah, 1999)
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be an AEC satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
\(\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\)
\(\beth_{\omega_1}\)
Upward Categoricity Transfer (Grossberg-V, 2006)
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\chi\)-tame for some \(\chi\geq LS(\mathcal{K})\) and is categorical in some \(\lambda^+> LS(\mathcal{K})+\chi^+\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\lambda^+\leq\mu\).
\(LS(\mathcal{K})\)
categoricity in \(\lambda^+\)
\(LS(\mathcal{K})+\chi^+\)
categoricity in \(\lambda^+\)
\(\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)
19
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\beth_{\omega_1}<\mu<\lambda^+\).
Downward Categoricity Transfer (Shelah, 1999)
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be an AEC satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
\(\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\)
\(\beth_{\omega_1}\)
Upward Categoricity Transfer (Grossberg-V, 2006)
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\chi\)-tame for some \(\chi\geq LS(\mathcal{K})\) and is categorical in some \(\lambda^+> LS(\mathcal{K})+\chi^+\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\lambda^+\leq\mu\).
\(LS(\mathcal{K})\)
categoricity in \(\lambda^+\)
\(LS(\mathcal{K})+\chi^+\)
categoricity in \(\mu\)
\(\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)
19
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\beth_{\omega_1}<\mu<\lambda^+\).
Downward Categoricity Transfer (Shelah, 1999)
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be an AEC satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
\(\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\)
\(\beth_{\omega_1}\)
Upward Categoricity Transfer (Grossberg-V, 2006)
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\chi\)-tame for some \(\chi\geq LS(\mathcal{K})\) and is categorical in some \(\lambda^+> LS(\mathcal{K})+\chi^+\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\lambda^+\leq\mu\).
\(LS(\mathcal{K})\)
categoricity in \(\lambda^+\)
Upward and Downward Bounds Improved (Vasey, 2017)
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(LS(\mathcal{K})\)-tame and is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>LS(\mathcal{K})\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu>min(\lambda,\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+})\).
\(\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)
\(LS(\mathcal{K})+\chi^+\)
categoricity in \(\lambda^+\)
19
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\beth_{\omega_1}<\mu<\lambda^+\).
Downward Categoricity Transfer (Shelah, 1999)
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be an AEC satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
\(\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\)
\(\beth_{\omega_1}\)
Upward Categoricity Transfer (Grossberg-V, 2006)
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\chi\)-tame for some \(\chi\geq LS(\mathcal{K})\) and is categorical in some \(\lambda^+> LS(\mathcal{K})+\chi^+\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\lambda^+\leq\mu\).
\(LS(\mathcal{K})\)
categoricity in \(\lambda^+\)
Upward and Downward Bounds Improved (Vasey, 2017)
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(LS(\mathcal{K})\)-tame and is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>LS(\mathcal{K})\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu>min(\lambda,\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+})\).
\(\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)
\(LS(\mathcal{K})+\chi^+\)
categoricity in \(\mu\)
19
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\beth_{\omega_1}<\mu<\lambda^+\).
Downward Categoricity Transfer (Shelah, 1999)
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be an AEC satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
\(\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\)
\(\beth_{\omega_1}\)
Upward Categoricity Transfer (Grossberg-V, 2006)
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\chi\)-tame for some \(\chi\geq LS(\mathcal{K})\) and is categorical in some \(\lambda^+> LS(\mathcal{K})+\chi^+\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\lambda^+\leq\mu\).
\(LS(\mathcal{K})\)
categoricity in \(\lambda^+\)
Upward and Downward Bounds Improved (Vasey, 2017)
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(LS(\mathcal{K})\)-tame and is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>LS(\mathcal{K})\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu>min(\lambda,\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+})\).
\(\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)
\(LS(\mathcal{K})+\chi^+\)
categoricity in \(\mu\)
19
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\beth_{\omega_1}<\mu<\lambda^+\).
Downward Categoricity Transfer (Shelah, 1999)
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be an AEC satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
\(\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\)
\(\beth_{\omega_1}\)
Upward Categoricity Transfer (Grossberg-V, 2006)
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\chi\)-tame for some \(\chi\geq LS(\mathcal{K})\) and is categorical in some \(\lambda^+> LS(\mathcal{K})+\chi^+\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\lambda^+\leq\mu\).
\(LS(\mathcal{K})\)
categoricity in \(\lambda^+\)
Upward and Downward Bounds Improved (Vasey, 2017)
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(LS(\mathcal{K})\)-tame and is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>LS(\mathcal{K})\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu>min(\lambda,\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+})\).
\(\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)
\(LS(\mathcal{K})+\chi^+\)
categoricity in \(\lambda^+\)
19
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\beth_{\omega_1}<\mu<\lambda^+\).
Downward Categoricity Transfer (Shelah, 1999)
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be an AEC satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
\(\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\)
\(\beth_{\omega_1}\)
Upward Categoricity Transfer (Grossberg-V, 2006)
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\chi\)-tame for some \(\chi\geq LS(\mathcal{K})\) and is categorical in some \(\lambda^+> LS(\mathcal{K})+\chi^+\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\lambda^+\leq\mu\).
\(LS(\mathcal{K})\)
categoricity in \(\mu\)
Upward and Downward Bounds Improved (Vasey, 2017)
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(LS(\mathcal{K})\)-tame and is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>LS(\mathcal{K})\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu>min(\lambda,\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+})\).
\(\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)
\(LS(\mathcal{K})+\chi^+\)
19
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\beth_{\omega_1}<\mu<\lambda^+\).
Downward Categoricity Transfer (Shelah, 1999)
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be an AEC satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
\(\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\)
\(\beth_{\omega_1}\)
Upward Categoricity Transfer (Grossberg-V, 2006)
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\chi\)-tame for some \(\chi\geq LS(\mathcal{K})\) and is categorical in some \(\lambda^+> LS(\mathcal{K})+\chi^+\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\lambda^+\leq\mu\).
\(LS(\mathcal{K})\)
categoricity in \(\mu\)
Upward and Downward Bounds Improved (Vasey, 2017)
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(LS(\mathcal{K})\)-tame and is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>LS(\mathcal{K})\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu>min(\lambda,\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+})\).
\(\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)
\(LS(\mathcal{K})+\chi^+\)
\(\lambda^+\)
\(\chi\)-tame
AP, JEP, and NMM
19
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\beth_{\omega_1}<\mu<\lambda^+\).
Downward Categoricity Transfer (Shelah, 1999)
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be an AEC satisfying AP, JEP, and NMM.
Upward Categoricity Transfer (Grossberg-V, 2006)
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\chi\)-tame for some \(\chi\geq LS(\mathcal{K})\) and is categorical in some \(\lambda^+> LS(\mathcal{K})+\chi^+\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu\) satisfying \(\lambda^+\leq\mu\).
Upward and Downward Bounds Improved (Vasey, 2017)
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(LS(\mathcal{K})\)-tame and is categorical in some \(\lambda^+>LS(\mathcal{K})\), then it is categorical in all \(\mu>min(\lambda,\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+})\).
\(\lambda^+\)
\(\chi\)-tame
AP, JEP, and NMM
20
\(\lambda^+\)
\(\chi\)-tame
AP, JEP, and NMM
follow from categoricity
successor assumption removed in categoricity cardinal
follows from categoricity
What the downward/upward results leave open...
\(\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\)
\(\beth_{\omega_1}\)
\(\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)
20
20
Categoricity for Universal Classes (Vasey 2017)
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be a universal class with \(LS(\mathcal{K})=\aleph_0\).
\(\lambda^+\)
\(\chi\)-tame
AP, JEP, and NMM
follow from categoricity
successor assumption removed in categoricity cardinal
follows from categoricity
What the downward/upward results leave open...
\(\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\)
\(\beth_{\omega_1}\)
\(\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)
20
\(\lambda^+\)
\(\chi\)-tame
AP, JEP, and NMM
follow from categoricity
successor assumption removed in categoricity cardinal
follows from categoricity
What the downward/upward results leave open...
Categoricity for Universal Classes (Vasey 2017)
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be a universal class with \(LS(\mathcal{K})=\aleph_0\).
\(\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\)
\(\beth_{\omega_1}\)
\(\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)
20
What the downward/upward results leave open...
\(\lambda^+\)
\(\chi\)-tame
AP, JEP, and NMM
follow from categoricity
successor assumption removed in categoricity cardinal
follows from categoricity
What the downward/upward results leave open...
Categoricity for Universal Classes (Vasey 2017)
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be a universal class with \(LS(\mathcal{K})=\aleph_0\).
\(\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\)
\(\beth_{\omega_1}\)
\(\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)
\(\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\)
\(\beth_{\omega_1}\)
\(\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)
20
What the downward/upward results leave open...
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be a universal class with \(LS(\mathcal{K})=\aleph_0\). If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in some \(\lambda>\beth_{\beth_{\omega_1}}\) then \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in all \(\lambda>\beth_{\beth_{\omega_1}}\).
\(\lambda^+\)
\(\chi\)-tame
AP, JEP, and NMM
follow from categoricity
successor assumption removed in categoricity cardinal
follows from categoricity
What the downward/upward results leave open...
Categoricity for Universal Classes (Vasey 2017)
\(\beth_{\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}}\)
\(\beth_{\omega_1}\)
\(\beth_{(2^{LS(\mathcal{K})})^+}\)
20
Limit Models
\(M_0\)
\(M_i\)
\(M_{i+1}\)
. . .
. . .
Definition (Shelah). If there exists a \(\prec\)-increasing sequence \(\langle M_i\in\mathcal{K}_\mu\mid i<\theta\rangle\) so that for each \(i<\theta\), \(M_{i+1}\) is universal over \(M_i\), then \(\bigcup_{i<\theta}M_i\) is a \((\mu,\theta)\)-limit model.
\(\bigcup_{i<\theta}M_{i}\)
21
Limit Models
\(M_0\)
\(M_i\)
\(M_{i+1}\)
. . .
. . .
\(M'\)
Definition (Shelah). If there exists a \(\prec\)-increasing sequence \(\langle M_i\in\mathcal{K}_\mu\mid i<\theta\rangle\) so that for each \(i<\theta\), \(M_{i+1}\) is universal over \(M_i\), then \(\bigcup_{i<\theta}M_i\) is a \((\mu,\theta)\)-limit model.
\(\bigcup_{i<\theta}M_{i}\)
21
Limit Models
\(M_0\)
\(M_i\)
\(M_{i+1}\)
. . .
. . .
\(M'\)
\(f\)
\(f(M')\)
Definition (Shelah). If there exists a \(\prec\)-increasing sequence \(\langle M_i\in\mathcal{K}_\mu\mid i<\theta\rangle\) so that for each \(i<\theta\), \(M_{i+1}\) is universal over \(M_i\), then \(\bigcup_{i<\theta}M_i\) is a \((\mu,\theta)\)-limit model.
\(\bigcup_{i<\theta}M_{i}\)
21
Limit Models
Definition (Shelah). If there exists a \(\prec\)-increasing sequence \(\langle M_i\in\mathcal{K}_\mu\mid i<\theta\rangle\) so that for each \(i<\theta\), \(M_{i+1}\) is universal over \(M_i\), then \(\bigcup_{i<\theta}M_i\) is a \((\mu,\theta)\)-limit model.
\(M_0\)
\(M_i\)
\(M_{i+1}\)
. . .
. . .
\(\bigcup_{i<\theta}M_{i}\)
\(M'\)
\(f\)
\(f(M')\)
\(f\restriction M_i=id_{M_i}\)
21
Uniqueness of Limit Models
Suppose that \(\alpha\) and \(\theta\) are limit ordinals \(<\mu^+\) and \(M\in\mathcal{K}_\mu\).
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be an AEC and fix \(\mu>LS(\mathcal{K})\).
Uniqueness question: Under what non-trivial conditions can we conclude that if \(M^\alpha\) is a \((\mu,\alpha)\)-limit model over \(M\) and \(M^\theta\) is a \((\mu,\theta)\)-limit model over \(M\), then there exists \(f:M^\alpha\cong M^\theta\) with \(f\restriction M=id_M\)?
\(M=M^\alpha_0\)
\(M^\alpha_{i+1}\)
\(M^\alpha_{i}\)
\(M^\alpha=\bigcup_{i<\alpha} M^\alpha_i\)
22
Uniqueness of Limit Models
Suppose that \(\alpha\) and \(\theta\) are limit ordinals \(<\mu^+\) and \(M\in\mathcal{K}_\mu\).
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be an AEC and fix \(\mu>LS(\mathcal{K})\).
\(M=M^\theta_0=M^\alpha_0\)
\(M^\theta_i\)
\(M^\theta_{i+1}\)
. . .
. . .
\(\bigcup_{i<\theta}M^\theta_{i}\)
\(M^\alpha_{i+1}\)
\(M^\alpha_{i}\)
\(M^\alpha=\bigcup_{i<\alpha} M^\alpha_i\)
Uniqueness question: Under what non-trivial conditions can we conclude that if \(M^\alpha\) is a \((\mu,\alpha)\)-limit model over \(M\) and \(M^\theta\) is a \((\mu,\theta)\)-limit model over \(M\), then there exists \(f:M^\alpha\cong M^\theta\) with \(f\restriction M=id_M\)?
22
Uniqueness of Limit Models
Suppose that \(\alpha\) and \(\theta\) are limit ordinals \(<\mu^+\) and \(M\in\mathcal{K}_\mu\).
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be an AEC and fix \(\mu>LS(\mathcal{K})\).
\(M=M^\theta_0=M^\alpha_0\)
\(M^\theta_i\)
\(M^\theta_{i+1}\)
. . .
. . .
\(\bigcup_{i<\theta}M^\theta_{i}\)
\(M^\alpha_{i+1}\)
\(M^\alpha_{i}\)
\(M^\alpha=\bigcup_{i<\alpha} M^\alpha_i\)
\(f\)
Uniqueness question: Under what non-trivial conditions can we conclude that if \(M^\alpha\) is a \((\mu,\alpha)\)-limit model over \(M\) and \(M^\theta\) is a \((\mu,\theta)\)-limit model over \(M\), then there exists \(f:M^\alpha\cong M^\theta\) with \(f\restriction M=id_M\)?
22
Uniqueness of Limit Models
Suppose that \(\alpha\) and \(\theta\) are limit ordinals \(<\mu^+\) and \(M\in\mathcal{K}_\mu\).
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be an AEC with AP, JEP, and NMM, and fix \(\mu>LS(\mathcal{K})\).
Case \(cf(\alpha)=cf(\theta)\): Back and forth construction produces \(f\).
Case \(cf(\alpha)\neq cf(\theta)\): Answer seems related to "superstability".
Uniqueness question: Under what non-trivial conditions can we conclude that if \(M^\alpha\) is a \((\mu,\alpha)\)-limit model over \(M\) and \(M^\theta\) is a \((\mu,\theta)\)-limit model over \(M\), then there exists \(f:M^\alpha\cong M^\theta\) with \(f\restriction M=id_M\)?
23
Some Answers in Categorical Settings
Answer #1: Infinitary Logic
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in \(\lambda>LS(\mathcal{K})\) and \(\mathcal{K}=Mod(\psi)\) where \(\psi\in L_{\kappa,\omega}\)
- for \(\kappa\) is strongly compact (Makkai-Shelah, 1990)
- for \(\kappa\) is measurable and \(\mu<\lambda\) (Kolman-Shelah, 1996)
Uniqueness question: Under what non-trivial conditions can we conclude that if \(M^\alpha\) is a \((\mu,\alpha)\)-limit model over \(M\) and \(M^\theta\) is a \((\mu,\theta)\)-limit model over \(M\), then there exists \(f:M^\alpha\cong M^\theta\) with \(f\restriction M=id_M\)?
24
Some Answers in Categorical Settings
Uniqueness question: Under what non-trivial conditions can we conclude that if \(M^\alpha\) is a \((\mu,\alpha)\)-limit model over \(M\) and \(M^\theta\) is a \((\mu,\theta)\)-limit model over \(M\), then there exists \(f:M^\alpha\cong M^\theta\) with \(f\restriction M=id_M\)?
Answer # 2: AECs with set theoretic assumptions
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in \(\lambda>LS(\mathcal{K})\) and has NMM.
- (Shelah-Villaveces, 1999) attempt uses GCH and diamond.
- GCH implies density of amalgamation bases
- Limit models are amalgamation bases and dense
- Categoricity implies no long splitting chains (Boney-Grossberg-V-Vasey, 2017).
- No long splitting chains implies uniqueness of limit models.
25
Some Answers in Categorical Settings
Uniqueness question: Under what non-trivial conditions can we conclude that if \(M^\alpha\) is a \((\mu,\alpha)\)-limit model over \(M\) and \(M^\theta\) is a \((\mu,\theta)\)-limit model over \(M\), then there exists \(f:M^\alpha\cong M^\theta\) with \(f\restriction M=id_M\)?
Answer # 2: AECs with set theoretic assumptions
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in \(\lambda>LS(\mathcal{K})\) and has NMM.
- (Shelah-Villaveces, 1999) attempt uses GCH and diamond.
- GCH implies density of amalgamation bases
- Limit models are amalgamation bases and dense
- Categoricity implies no long splitting chains (Boney-Grossberg-V-Vasey, 2017).
- No long splitting chains implies uniqueness of limit models.
25
Some Answers in Categorical Settings
Uniqueness question: Under what non-trivial conditions can we conclude that if \(M^\alpha\) is a \((\mu,\alpha)\)-limit model over \(M\) and \(M^\theta\) is a \((\mu,\theta)\)-limit model over \(M\), then there exists \(f:M^\alpha\cong M^\theta\) with \(f\restriction M=id_M\)?
Answer # 2: AECs with set theoretic assumptions
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in \(\lambda>LS(\mathcal{K})\) and has NMM.
- (Shelah-Villaveces, 1999) attempt uses GCH and diamond.
- GCH implies density of amalgamation bases
- Limit models are amalgamation bases and dense (V 2006)
- Categoricity implies no long splitting chains (Boney-Grossberg-V-Vasey, 2017).
- No long splitting chains implies uniqueness of limit models.
25
Some Answers in Categorical Settings
Uniqueness question: Under what non-trivial conditions can we conclude that if \(M^\alpha\) is a \((\mu,\alpha)\)-limit model over \(M\) and \(M^\theta\) is a \((\mu,\theta)\)-limit model over \(M\), then there exists \(f:M^\alpha\cong M^\theta\) with \(f\restriction M=id_M\)?
Answer # 2: AECs with set theoretic assumptions
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in \(\lambda>LS(\mathcal{K})\) and has NMM.
- (Shelah-Villaveces, 1999) attempt uses GCH and diamond.
- GCH implies density of amalgamation bases
- Limit models are amalgamation bases and dense (V 2006)
- Categoricity implies no long splitting chains (Boney-Grossberg-V-Vasey, 2017).
- No long splitting chains implies uniqueness of limit models.
25
Some Answers in Categorical Settings
Uniqueness question: Under what non-trivial conditions can we conclude that if \(M^\alpha\) is a \((\mu,\alpha)\)-limit model over \(M\) and \(M^\theta\) is a \((\mu,\theta)\)-limit model over \(M\), then there exists \(f:M^\alpha\cong M^\theta\) with \(f\restriction M=id_M\)?
Answer # 2: AECs with set theoretic assumptions
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in \(\lambda>LS(\mathcal{K})\) and has NMM.
- (Shelah-Villaveces, 1999) attempt uses GCH and diamond.
- GCH implies density of amalgamation bases
- Limit models are amalgamation bases and dense (V 2006)
- Categoricity implies no long splitting chains (Boney-Grossberg-V-Vasey, 2017).
- No long splitting chains implies uniqueness of limit models (and \(\mu\)-symmetry.) (V, 2006, 2013, 2016)
25
Some Answers in Categorical Settings
Answer #3: AECs with no set theoretic assumptions
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is categorical in \(\lambda\) sufficiently large and \(\mathcal{K}\) satisfies AP and JEP, then \(\mathcal{K}\) has uniqueness of limit models of cardinality \(\mu\) for \(\mu\geq LS(\mathcal{K})\). (Vasey-V, 2017)
Uniqueness question: Under what non-trivial conditions can we conclude that if \(M^\alpha\) is a \((\mu,\alpha)\)-limit model over \(M\) and \(M^\theta\) is a \((\mu,\theta)\)-limit model over \(M\), then there exists \(f:M^\alpha\cong M^\theta\) with \(f\restriction M=id_M\)?
26
Some Answers in Superstable Settings
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\mu\)-superstable and satisfies AP, JEP, NMM and is tame and stable in a proper class of cardinals (Grossberg-Vasey, 2017)
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\mu\)-superstable and satisfies AP, JEP, NMM and satisfies \(\mu\)-symmetry (V., 2016).
Answer # 4: in Superstable Settings:
Uniqueness question: Under what non-trivial conditions can we conclude that if \(M^\alpha\) is a \((\mu,\alpha)\)-limit model over \(M\) and \(M^\theta\) is a \((\mu,\theta)\)-limit model over \(M\), then there exists \(f:M^\alpha\cong M^\theta\) with \(f\restriction M=id_M\)?
27
Focusing on Superstability
If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\mu\)- and \(\mu^+\)-superstable and satisfies AP, JEP, NMM
\(\mu^+\)-symmetry
(Vasey-V., 2017)
\(\mu\)-symmetry
Uniqueness of limit models of cardinality \(\mu^+\)
Union of increasing chain of \(\mu^+\)-saturated models is saturated
Uniqueness of limit models of cardinality \(\mu\)
(V., 2016b)
(V., 2016b)
(V., 2016b)
(V., 2016a)
(V., 2016a)
28
circa 2007
Abstract Elementary Classes
Classification Theory for
Tame
Categorical in high enough cardinality
Stable
Superstable
29
Tame Abstract Elementary Classes
Classification Theory for
Tame
Categorical in high enough cardinality
Stable
Superstable
29
circa 2007
Superstability in Tame AECs
Suppose \(\mathcal{K}\) satisfies the AP, JEP, and NMM and is tame. If \(\mathcal{K}\) is stable in unboundedly many cardinals, then TFAE:
- For \(\lambda\) high enough, \(\mathcal{K}\) has uniqueness of limit models of cardinality \(\lambda\).
- For \(\lambda\) high enough, \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\lambda\)-superstable.
- For \(\lambda\) high enough, the union of a chain of \(\lambda\)-saturated models in \(\lambda\) saturated.
- There is a \(\theta\) so that for \(\lambda\) high enough, \(\mathcal{K}\) is \((\lambda,\theta)\)-solvable.
- For \(\lambda\) high enough, there is \(\kappa=\kappa_\lambda\leq\lambda\) so that there is a good \(\lambda\)-frame on \(\mathcal{K}^{\kappa-sat}_\lambda\).
- For \(\lambda\) high enough, \(\mathcal{K}\) has a superlimit model of cardinality \(\lambda\).
See (Boney-Vasey, 2017) for an exposition.
30
Limit Models without Superstabilty
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be an AEC with AP, JEP, and NMM. \(M\in\mathcal{K_\lambda}\) is \(\lambda\)-saturated iff \(M\) is a \((\lambda,\lambda)\)-limit model (Grossberg-Vasey, 2017).
For \(\mathcal{K}\) an AEC with AP, JEP, and NMM. If \(\mathcal{K}\) is \(\mu\)-stable, has weak continuity of \(\mu\)-splitting, and satisfies \(\mu\)-symmetry, then there is a \(\kappa\) which for \(\alpha_l\) \((l=1,2)\) of cofinality \(>\kappa\), then \((\mu,\alpha_1)\) limit models are isomorphic to \((\mu,\alpha_2)\)-limit models. (Boney-V., nd)
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be the class of torsion free Abelian groups with the pure subgroup relation. If \(G\in\mathcal{K}\) is a \((\lambda,\alpha)\)-limit model, then
- for \(cf(\alpha)\) uncountable, \(G\cong (\bigoplus_\lambda\mathbb{Q})\bigoplus\Pi_{p\; prime}\overline{(\bigoplus_\lambda\mathbb{Z}_{(p)})}\)
-
for \(cf(\alpha)\) countable, \(G\) is not algebraically compact
(Mazari-Armida, 2018).
31
Uniqueness of Limit Models in Algebraic Settings
Given a ring \(R\), let \(\mathcal{K}\) be the set of left \(R\)-modules.
\(R\) is left Noetherian \(\Leftrightarrow\) \(\mathcal{K}\) is superstable \(\Leftrightarrow\)
Given a ring \(R\), let \(\mathcal{K}\) be the set of flat left \(R\)-modules with pure embeddings.
\(R\) is left perfect \(\Leftrightarrow\) \(\mathcal{K}\) is superstable \(\Leftrightarrow\)
Let \(\mathcal{K}\) be the class of Abelian groups with the subgroup relation. Then \(\mathcal{K}\) has uniqueness of limit models in every infinite cardinality (Mazari-Armida, 2018).
Limit models are unique in some cardinality \(\lambda>(|R|+\aleph_0)^+\) (Mazari-Armida, 2021).
Limit models are unique in all cardinalities \(\lambda\geq(|R|+\aleph_0)^+\) (Mazari-Armida, 2020)
32
20 Years of Tameness +
Honors Program
33
20 Years of Tameness +
34
20 Years of Tameness
By Monica VanDieren
20 Years of Tameness
- 340