Politics through the Lens of Economics

Lecture 8: Condorcet Jury Theorem

30 November, 2016

Masayuki Kudamatsu

Discussion time for written assignment

What evidence do we need to say

the probabilistic voting model explains

The welfare state in Sweden

Publicly-funded healthcare (capped annual fee at 1100 SEK)

Primary, secondary, and higher education for free

Unemployment benefits (80% of income for first 200 days)

Parental leave (80% of income for 480 days)

etc.

Discussion time for written assignment

Aim to fail gracefully

by coming up with wrong answers

Motivation for today

Policies that increase everyone's income

e.g.

Jury trial (i.e. convict those who did commit a crime)

In the previous lectures

we discussed policy issues with conflict of interest among citizens

Today and the following three lectures

we look at policy issues with common interest among citizens

Motivation for today

In the previous lectures

we discussed policy issues with conflict of interest among citizens

Today and the following three lectures

we look at policy issues with common interest among citizens

Today and next week

when no one knows for sure which policy is correct 

Lectures 10-11

when politicians' interest conflicts with citizens'

Today's Road Map

Condorcet Jury Theorem

Robustness to Strategic Voting 

Evidence

Today's Road Map

Condorcet Jury Theorem

Robustness to Strategic Voting 

Evidence

Condorcet Jury Theorem

Majority voting is more likely to choose a "good policy"

than a single person's decision

"good policy" = preferred by everyone 

It was a statistical theory

by French philosopher Condorcet

in the late 18th century

to defend the French Revolution

Illustrative Example

3 persons, choosing policies A or B

Policy A is correct (but no one knows for sure)

60% of the time each person can tell which policy is correct

Think of % as how smart or educated each person is

e.g. Amend Article 9 of the Constitution of Japan or not

e.g. Foreign invasion will be prevented by amendment (or not)

1

A

B

60% of the time

single person's decision is correct

40% of the time

wrong

Single person's decision

1

A

B

2

A

B

When person 1 is correct

60% of the time

person 2 is correct

40%

wrong

1

A

B

2

A

B

3

A

B

When persons 1 & 2 are correct

60% correct

40% wrong

1

A

B

2

A

B

3

A

B

Majority voting outcome

A

A

1

A

B

2

A

B

3

A

B

Majority voting outcome

A

A

A

B

60%

40%

When person 1 is correct and person 2 is wrong

1

A

B

2

A

B

3

A

B

Majority voting outcome

A

A

A

B

A

B

1

A

B

2

A

B

3

A

B

Majority voting outcome

A

A

A

B

A

B

B

A

When person 1

is wrong

1

A

B

2

A

B

3

A

B

Majority voting outcome

A

A

A

B

A

B

B

A

A

B

When 1

is wrong

and 2

is correct

1

A

B

2

A

B

3

A

B

Majority voting outcome

A

A

A

B

A

B

B

A

A

B

A

B

1

A

B

2

A

B

3

A

B

Majority voting outcome

A

A

A

B

A

B

B

A

A

B

A

B

B

A

B

B

1

A

B

Majority voting is correct

correct

60% of the time

single person's decision is correct

Majority voting outcome

A

A

A

B

A

B

B

B

1

A

B

Majority voting is correct

correct

60% of the time

single person's decision is correct

Majority voting

is correct

more likely if  

               is longer

than 

Majority voting outcome

A

A

A

B

A

B

B

B

1

A

B

2

A

B

3

A

B

Majority voting outcome

A

A

B

A

These two events happen

with the same frequency

i.e. 60% x 40% = 24%

B

A

B

B

1

A

B

2

A

B

3

A

B

Majority voting outcome

A

A

B

A

B

A

B

B

A

A

Same frequency

(60x40x60=14.4%)

1

A

B

2

A

B

3

A

B

Majority voting outcome

A

A

B

A

B

A

B

B

Same frequency

(60x40x40=9.6%)

B

B

1

A

B

2

A

B

3

A

B

Majority voting outcome

A

A

B

A

B

A

B

B

9.6%

B

B

A

A

14.4%

1

A

B

Majority voting is correct

correct

60% of the time

single person's decision is correct

Majority voting

is correct

more likely if  

               is longer

than 

Majority voting outcome

A

A

A

B

A

B

B

B

9.6%

14.4%

1

A

B

64.8% of the time

majority voting is correct

60% of the time

single person's decision is correct

Majority voting outcome

A

A

A

B

A

B

B

B

9.6%

14.4%

A

B

A

A

A

B

A

B

B

B

9.6%

14.4%

Majority voting is more likely

to choose the correct policy

than single person's decision !

A

B

A

A

A

B

A

B

B

B

This holds true (           is longer than        )

as long as each person is correct

more than half of the time

1

A

B

2

A

B

3

A

B

Majority voting outcome

A

A

B

A

B

A

B

B

Wrong

B

B

A

A

Wrong

Correct

Correct

Correct & Wrong

Correct & Wrong

A

B

A

B

Today's Road Map

Condorcet Jury Theorem

Robustness to Strategic Voting

Evidence

Condorcet Jury Theorem assumes "sincere voting"

Each voter votes for the policy that he/she learns is correct

Learning A is correct

Learning B is correct

Vote for A

Vote for B

Economists assume "strategic voting"

with 3 people voting,

your vote matters only when two others vote differently

Voters consider the situation where they are "pivotal"

Both vote for A

One votes for A

None votes for A

A gets majority

B gets majority

Your vote decides

Economists assume "strategic voting"

with 3 people voting,

your vote matters only when two others vote differently

Voters consider the situation where they are "pivotal"

This situation itself

gives you information

To understand this argument

we need to learn a statistical concept used by economists:

Bayesian updating

Today's economics lesson

Bayesian Updating

A

B

Suppose that you believe that policy A is correct

60% of the time

60%

40%

Your initial belief

Today's economics lesson

Bayesian Updating

A

B

Now you examine which policy is really correct

60%

40%

Your initial belief

Today's economics lesson

Bayesian Updating

A

B

60%

40%

A

B

Your learning outcome when A is correct

80%

20%

A

B

Suppose that you discover the correct policy 80% of the time

Your initial belief

Today's economics lesson

Bayesian Updating

A

60%

40%

when B is correct

A

B

A

20%

B

80%

Your learning outcome 

Your initial belief

Today's economics lesson

Bayesian Updating

A

B

60%

40%

A

B

Your learning outcome

80%

20%

A

B

A

20%

B

80%

Your initial belief

Today's economics lesson

Bayesian Updating

A

B

60%

40%

B

Suppose you've learned that B is correct

20%

A

B

80%

B

Your initial belief

Today's economics lesson

Bayesian Updating

A

B

60%

40%

B

60x20=12%

A

B

40x80=32%

B

This happens more likely

when correct policy is B

Your initial belief

Today's economics lesson

Bayesian Updating

A

B

60%

40%

B

60x20=12%

A

B

40x80=32%

B

You now believe that B is more likely to be correct

Your initial belief

Today's economics lesson

Bayesian Updating

A

B

60%

40%

A

B

If you learn the correct policy only 50% of the time...

50%

50%

A

B

A

50%

B

50%

Your initial belief

Today's economics lesson

Bayesian Updating

A

B

60%

40%

B

Learning B is correct does not change your belief

60x50=30%

A

B

B

40x50=20%

Your initial belief

Today's economics lesson

Bayesian Updating

A

B

60%

40%

B

If your learning is correct 60% of the time...

60x40=24%

A

B

B

40x60=24%

B

Your initial belief

Today's economics lesson

Bayesian Updating

A

B

60%

40%

B

Learning B is correct changes your belief

when your learning is correct more than 60% of time

60x39=23.4%

A

B

B

40x61=24.4%

B

Your initial belief

Today's economics lesson

Bayesian Updating

70%

30%

A

B

If your initial belief is stronger...

Today's economics lesson

Bayesian Updating

A

B

70%

30%

B

70x30=21%

A

B

B

30x70=21%

If your initial belief is stronger...

B

your learning has to be

correct more frequently

to change the belief

A

B

Suppose every 3 person initially believes

policy A is correct 3 out of 4 times

3/4

1/4

Everyone's initial belief

Consider majority voting by 3 people

A

B

Now each voter examines which policy is really correct

Assume they find the correct answer 3 out of 5 times

3/4

1/4

Everyone's initial belief

Consider majority voting by 3 people

Suppose everyone finds out B is correct

A

B

Suppose everyone finds out B is correct

3/4

1/4

When A is correct policy...

\Leftarrow \big(1-\frac{3}{5}\big)^3 = \frac{8}{125}
(135)3=8125\Leftarrow \big(1-\frac{3}{5}\big)^3 = \frac{8}{125}

This happens 8 out of 125 times

8  :  117                                                           

BBB

A

B

Suppose everyone finds out B is correct

3/4

1/4

When B is correct policy...

BBB

\Leftarrow \big(\frac{3}{5}\big)^3 = \frac{27}{125}
(35)3=27125\Leftarrow \big(\frac{3}{5}\big)^3 = \frac{27}{125}

This happens 27 out of 125 times

27  :  98       

A

B

Suppose everyone finds out B is correct

3/4

1/4

Initial belief: A is correct more likely

BBB

BBB

\frac{3}{4} *\frac{8}{125}=\frac{24}{500}
348125=24500\frac{3}{4} *\frac{8}{125}=\frac{24}{500}
\frac{1}{4} *\frac{27}{125}=\frac{27}{500}
1427125=27500\frac{1}{4} *\frac{27}{125}=\frac{27}{500}

Updated belief: B is correct more likely

<

A

Suppose only 2 people find out B is correct

A

B

Suppose only 2 people find out B is correct

3/4

1/4

Initial belief: A is correct more likely

ABB

ABB

\frac{3}{4} *\big(\frac{3}{5}*\frac{2}{5}*\frac{2}{5}\big)=\frac{36}{500}
34(352525)=36500\frac{3}{4} *\big(\frac{3}{5}*\frac{2}{5}*\frac{2}{5}\big)=\frac{36}{500}
\frac{1}{4}*\big(\frac{2}{5}*\frac{3}{5}*\frac{3}{5}\big)=\frac{27}{500}
14(253535)=27500\frac{1}{4}*\big(\frac{2}{5}*\frac{3}{5}*\frac{3}{5}\big)=\frac{27}{500}

Updated belief: A is (still) correct more likely

A

>

Suppose only 1 person find out B is correct

A

B

Suppose only 1 person find out B is correct

3/4

1/4

Initial belief: A is correct more likely

AAB

AAB

\frac{3}{4} *\big(\frac{3}{5}*\frac{3}{5}*\frac{2}{5}\big)=\frac{54}{500}
34(353525)=54500\frac{3}{4} *\big(\frac{3}{5}*\frac{3}{5}*\frac{2}{5}\big)=\frac{54}{500}
\frac{1}{4}*\big(\frac{2}{5}*\frac{2}{5}*\frac{3}{5}\big)=\frac{12}{500}
14(252535)=12500\frac{1}{4}*\big(\frac{2}{5}*\frac{2}{5}*\frac{3}{5}\big)=\frac{12}{500}

Updated belief: A is (still) correct more likely

A

>

Belief switches from A to B

only when all three people learn B is correct

(i.e. Initial belief in A is quite strong)

So in this example:

Optimal voting

When both of the other two vote for A

Majority voting yields policy B, irrespective of your vote

When both of the other two vote for B

Majority voting yields policy A, irrespective of your vote

Your vote is "pivotal"

When one votes for A and the other for B

Case 1

Case 2

Case 3

Focus on what's optimal for Case 3 only

A

Optimal voting

When one votes for A and the other for B

Case 3

You learn A is correct

A

B

3/4

1/4

AAB

AAB

\frac{3}{4} *\big(\frac{3}{5}*\frac{3}{5}*\frac{2}{5}\big)=\frac{54}{500}
34(353525)=54500\frac{3}{4} *\big(\frac{3}{5}*\frac{3}{5}*\frac{2}{5}\big)=\frac{54}{500}
\frac{1}{4}*\big(\frac{2}{5}*\frac{2}{5}*\frac{3}{5}\big)=\frac{12}{500}
14(252535)=12500\frac{1}{4}*\big(\frac{2}{5}*\frac{2}{5}*\frac{3}{5}\big)=\frac{12}{500}

A

>

It's optimal to vote for A

(i.e. Only 1 person finds B is correct)

Optimal voting

When one votes for A and the other for B

Case 3

A

B

It's optimal to vote for A, by ignoring the personal learning

B

3/4

1/4

ABB

ABB

\frac{3}{4} *\big(\frac{3}{5}*\frac{2}{5}*\frac{2}{5}\big)=\frac{36}{500}
34(352525)=36500\frac{3}{4} *\big(\frac{3}{5}*\frac{2}{5}*\frac{2}{5}\big)=\frac{36}{500}
\frac{1}{4}*\big(\frac{2}{5}*\frac{3}{5}*\frac{3}{5}\big)=\frac{27}{500}
14(253535)=27500\frac{1}{4}*\big(\frac{2}{5}*\frac{3}{5}*\frac{3}{5}\big)=\frac{27}{500}

A

>

You learn B is correct

(i.e. 2 people find B is correct)

Optimal voting

When one votes for A and the other for B

Case 3

Whatever learning outcome, it's optimal to vote for A

A

This is true for every voter

Policy A will be the majority voting outcome

even if every person learns B is correct

Condorcet Jury Theorem breaks down !

What if unanimity is needed to adopt policy B?

When both of the other two vote for A

When both of the other two vote for B

When one votes for A and the other for B

Case 1

Case 2

Case 3

Policy B is voted down anyway

Your vote is "pivotal"

Policy B is voted down anyway

Focus on what's optimal for Case 2 only

What if unanimity is needed to adopt policy B?

When both of the other two vote for B

Case 2

B

B

3/4

1/4

ABB

ABB

\frac{3}{4} *\big(\frac{3}{5}*\frac{2}{5}*\frac{2}{5}\big)=\frac{36}{500}
34(352525)=36500\frac{3}{4} *\big(\frac{3}{5}*\frac{2}{5}*\frac{2}{5}\big)=\frac{36}{500}
\frac{1}{4}*\big(\frac{2}{5}*\frac{3}{5}*\frac{3}{5}\big)=\frac{27}{500}
14(253535)=27500\frac{1}{4}*\big(\frac{2}{5}*\frac{3}{5}*\frac{3}{5}\big)=\frac{27}{500}

A

>

It's optimal to vote for A, by following the personal learning

You learn A is correct

(i.e. 2 people find B is correct)

What if unanimity is needed to adopt policy B?

When both of the other two vote for B

Case 2

It's optimal to vote for B, by following the personal learning

B

3/4

1/4

BBB

BBB

\frac{3}{4} *\frac{8}{125}=\frac{24}{500}
348125=24500\frac{3}{4} *\frac{8}{125}=\frac{24}{500}
\frac{1}{4} *\frac{27}{125}=\frac{27}{500}
1427125=27500\frac{1}{4} *\frac{27}{125}=\frac{27}{500}

<

A

You learn B is correct

(i.e. 3 people find B is correct)

What if unanimity is needed to adopt policy B?

When both of the other two vote for B

Case 2

It's optimal to vote according to your learning outcome

This is true for every voter

Policy B will be adopted

exactly when B is more likely to be correct

(i.e. everyone learns B is correct)

For personal learning to be reflected in voting

the voting rule must be as follows:

When at least m out of n persons find B is correct,

the more-likely-to-be-correct policy switches from A to B

B is adopted if at least m out of n persons vote for B

cf. Article 96 of the Constitution of Japan 

"Amendments to this Constitution shall be initiated by the Diet, through a concurring vote of two-thirds or more of all the members of each House..."

Prime Minister Shinzo Abe once remarked:

"It's unfair that just more than one-third of lawmakers could block revisions even if 50 percent or more of the public want to amend the Constitution..."

What we've learned suggests: it's not about "fairness"

but whether the voting rule aggregates information

Today's Road Map

Condorcet Jury Theorem

Robustness to Strategic Voting 

Evidence

Do people really vote strategically?

Lab experiments with students at Caltech

Do people really vote strategically?

Lab experiments with students at Caltech

Generalizable to the general population?

Do people really vote strategically?

Lab experiments with students at Caltech

1. Each subject forms a group with 2 others (randomly matched)

2. Each group is ramdomly assigned

either a red or blue jar,

without subjects knowing which

Think of the jar as the correct policy

The blue jar contains 7 blue balls and 3 red balls

The red jar contains 7 red balls and 3 blue balls.

Think of each ball as a personal learning outcome

Your learning is correct 70% of the time

3. Each subject selects one ball, at random, from the jar.

Its colour is then revealed.

4. Each member votes for either a red jar or a blue jar

5. If the voting result is correct, everyone in the group earns 50 cents. If wrong, only 5 cents.

OR

after the voting rule (majority or unanimity) is assigned

Red jar is chosen with 2 out of 3 votes under majority voting

3 out of 3 votes under unanimity voting

B

1/2

1/2

Initial belief: A (blue jar) and B (red jar) are equally likely to be correct

A

Theoretical predictions

B

1/2

1/2

ABB

ABB

A

If two people find B is correct

Initial belief: A (blue jar) and B (red jar) are equally likely to be correct

B

1/2

1/2

ABB

ABB

\frac{1}{2} *\big(\frac{7}{10}*\frac{3}{10}*\frac{3}{10}\big)=\frac{63}{2000}
12(710310310)=632000\frac{1}{2} *\big(\frac{7}{10}*\frac{3}{10}*\frac{3}{10}\big)=\frac{63}{2000}
\frac{1}{2}*\big(\frac{7}{10}*\frac{7}{10}*\frac{3}{10}\big)=\frac{147}{2000}
12(710710310)=1472000\frac{1}{2}*\big(\frac{7}{10}*\frac{7}{10}*\frac{3}{10}\big)=\frac{147}{2000}

Updated belief: B (red jar) is correct more likely

A

If two people find B is correct

Initial belief: A (blue jar) and B (red jar) are equally likely to be correct

B

1/2

1/2

AAB

AAB

A

If only one person finds B is correct 

Initial belief: A (blue jar) and B (red jar) are equally likely to be correct

B

1/2

1/2

AAB

AAB

\frac{1}{2} *\big(\frac{7}{10}*\frac{3}{10}*\frac{3}{10}\big)=\frac{63}{2000}
12(710310310)=632000\frac{1}{2} *\big(\frac{7}{10}*\frac{3}{10}*\frac{3}{10}\big)=\frac{63}{2000}
\frac{1}{2}*\big(\frac{7}{10}*\frac{7}{10}*\frac{3}{10}\big)=\frac{147}{2000}
12(710710310)=1472000\frac{1}{2}*\big(\frac{7}{10}*\frac{7}{10}*\frac{3}{10}\big)=\frac{147}{2000}

Updated belief: A (blue jar) is correct more likely

A

If only one person finds B is correct 

Initial belief: A (blue jar) and B (red jar) are equally likely to be correct

B

The correct policy switches from blue jar to red jar

when two, instead of one, voters find red jar is correct

Under majority voting,

voters vote according to their learning outcome

Under unanimity voting,

voters ignore their learning outcome and always vote for red jar

Theoretical predictions

B

Under majority voting

5.7% after seeing the blue ball

97.2% after seeing the red ball

Experimental results

% of subjects who vote for the red jar

Source: Table 3 of Guarnaschelli et al. (2000)

B

Under unanimity voting

36% after seeing the blue ball

95.4% after seeing the red ball

Experimental results

% of subjects who vote for the red jar

Source: Table 3 of Guarnaschelli et al. (2000)

Summary

Majority voting picks the correct policy more likely

than a single person's decision

if the more-likely-to-be-correct policy switches from A to B

when a majority of voters learn that B is correct

People do seem to vote strategically

(i.e. ignoring their own learning outcome if the pivotal situation makes it optimal to do so)

Next lecture

Voter turnout

This lecture is based on the following academic articles:

Austen-Smith, David, and Jeffrey S. Banks. 1996. “Information Aggregation, Rationality, and the Condorcet Jury Theorem.” American Political Science Review 90(1): 34–45.

Guarnaschelli, Serena et al. 2000. “An Experimental Study of Jury Decision Rules.” American Political Science Review 94(2): 407–23.

Politics through the Lens of Economics: Lecture 8 Condorcet Jury Theorem

By Masayuki Kudamatsu

Politics through the Lens of Economics: Lecture 8 Condorcet Jury Theorem

  • 1,441